Sunday 23 December 2012

THE VALUE OF THE BEAUTIFUL TO LIFE


    THE VALUE OF ‘THE BEAUTIFUL’ TO LIFE
                                                                   Orjiebele Malachy
By ‘the Beautiful’ we re-echo the classical aesthetic understanding that takes it for granted that beauty is the only, or at least the fundamental term in ordinary language for ascribing aesthetic qualities. Thus ‘the beautiful’ is herewith used to refer to the aesthetic. The word aesthetic derives from the Greek word perceive. To perceive excellence adequately requires proper taste, which Webster defines as “the power of discerning and appreciating fitness, beauty, congruity, symmetry, or whatever constitutes excellence.”[1] It therefore amounts that we can as well render the topic of discussion to read ‘the Value of the Aesthetic to Life.’ What then can we refer to as ‘the beautiful’ in our experiences of the works of art and the works of nature since these - works of art and works of nature - constitute the domain of aesthetics?
In response to this question of the beautiful, most of those who have attempted to define beauty agree that it involves a response of pleasure. We call something beautiful when it delights us or pleases us in some special way. But what causes this response on our part? Is it something in the object itself? Is it merely a subjective reaction on our part? Or is it some combination of these two?
We know from common experience that all persons do not find the same objects beautiful. What pleases some fails to please others. This is sometimes taken to mean that beauty exists in the eye of the beholder. But it can also mean that when a person’s taste is cultivated, he or she is able to appreciate the elements of beauty in objects which fail to please others because they have not yet learned to appreciate that beauty.
In considering this issue, Leo Tolstoy has said that all the aesthetic definitions of beauty lead to two fundamental conceptions. The first he says “is that beauty is something having an independent existence (existing in itself), that it is one of the manifestations of the absolutely Perfect, of the Ideal, of the Spirit, of Will, or of God.”[2] This definition of his is exemplified in the writings of Plato, Fitche, Schelling, Hegel, Schopenhauer, and others.
The second definition “is that beauty is a kind of pleasure we receive which does not have personal advantage for its object or aim.”[3] This second definition of beauty finds favour chiefly among the English aesthetic writers like Lord Shaftesbury, Francis Hutcheson, Edmund Burke and so on, and later on finds a forceful interpretation in Immanuel Kant who takes disinterestedness to be the First Moment (Moment of Quality) of the Judgement of Taste, thus defining beauty as “simply a certain kind of disinterested pleasure received by us.”[4]
The distinguishing factor in both definitions is captured in the concept of disinterestedness. The term disinterested means that the pleasure is not concerned with further interests. Thus the aesthetic contemplator becomes the disinterested observer. Needless to say, this does not mean that aesthetic contemplation is uninteresting. If for example one regards a beautiful object as an object of desire or as a stimulant to desire, his point of view is not that of aesthetic contemplation; he is an ‘interested’ spectator. In point of fact he is the servant or instrument of the aesthetic object. But it is possible for him to regard the beautiful object neither as itself an object of desire nor as stimulant to desire but solely for its aesthetic significance. He is then a disinterested but not an uninterested spectator.
The point here is that disinterestedness informs what aesthetic perception and pleasure entails. Aesthetic pleasure is any and every experience directly enjoyed for its own quality.  It is thus to be distinguished from any and everything valued because of its instrumental effect, or merely because of its promise for the future. Instances of the beautiful thus include the enjoyment of a sunset or sunrise, a mountain view, music, painting, sculpture, dancing, or anything enjoyed as beautiful, and every perceived excellence if appreciated directly for this quality of excellence.
To illustrate, let us take for example the aesthetic experience of a sunset, the perception and enjoyment of its beauty. This pleasure is located directly and immediately in the experiencing itself. The beauty of the sunset enjoyed is, as Webster says of beauty in general, “that quality or aggregate of qualities in a thing which includes immediate and disinterested pleasure.”[5] In this enjoyment of the sunset is illustrated the action of the beautiful as distinguished from the merely pleasing and the pragmatic. Certainly the enjoyment of a sunset is ‘immediate’ and ‘disinterested’ and there is in it no element of the pragmatic.
Had music, instead of the sunset, been chosen as the example, almost the same discussion would have followed. We value music – certainly in general for the present enjoyment we get from it, not necessarily because it is otherwise useful. Music however has this difference from the sunset, that it is an art contrived by humans for the purpose of arousing aesthetic pleasure. Thus is illustrated in music the purport that “art comes to you professing frankly to give nothing but the highest quality to your moments as they pass, and simply for these moments’ sake.”[6]
To this point, Webster’s Synonyms says that “aesthetic satisfaction is the content that accompanies the enjoyment of beauty for its own sake, and independently of all other considerations.”[7]  Hence the word ‘beautiful’ both in learned and in ordinary use is applied to that which excites the keenest pleasure, not only of the senses but also, through the medium of the senses of mind and soul. Beautiful in the Synonyms “also suggest an approach to, or a realization of, perfection, often specifically the imagined perfection associated with ones conception of an ideal.”[8] That is why beautiful is not applicable to only to things that are directly perceived by the senses (as a beautiful woman; a beautiful scene…) but to things that are actually mental constructions; as a beautiful poem, a beautiful thought, a beautiful character and so on. John Dewey couches it in this way that “any practical activity will, provided it is integrated and moves by its own urge to fulfillment, have aesthetic quality.”[9]
It seems clear now that a much wider range of true aesthetic enjoyment is open to people generally than many hitherto thought. If so, do we not owe it to ourselves to explore such possibilities and find out what now thwarts the full realization of these potential pleasures? What possibilities are there for enriching life through extending the area of aesthetic enjoyment? And what is the value of ‘the beautiful’ to life?
In general the answer will lie along two lines: one, the cultivation of interest and sensitivity (taste) for various forms of aesthetic enjoyment; the other, the development of such creative construction or creative arrangement as being true aesthetic enjoyment from surveying the sequence of successful stages of each endeavour as it develops. The person with such interest works devotedly to attain his ideals, and enjoys aesthetically the several approximations thereto in the successive stages in the enterprise.
Now, cultivating a taste for the beautiful will greatly increase one’s capacity for joy and efficiency. Orisen Swett Marden[10] says that it is not enough to cultivate mere physical and intellectual strength. If the aesthetic side of one’s being, an appreciation of all that is beautiful in nature and art, is not fostered, life will be like a country without flowers or birds, sweet scents or sounds, colour or music. It may be strong, but it will lack the graces that would adorn its strength and make it attractive. A thing of beauty is a joy for every human being, and the one who cannot enjoy a marvelous painting a melodious song or a beautiful sunset is not fully human. The most civilized man is the one whose aesthetic faculties are best developed. The highest expression of civilization is the aspiration and love for the beautiful.
A love for the beautiful has a refreshing, softening, enriching influence upon character, which nothing else can supply. What an infinite satisfaction comes from beginning early in life to cultivate our finer qualities, to develop higher sentiments, purer tastes, delicate feelings, and the love of the beautiful in all its varied forms of expression![11] The story is told of a school teacher in Chicago who put up a ‘beauty corner’ for her pupils in the school. Among the little collection of fine photographs and paintings was a picture of the Sistine Madonna (i.e. an artistic representation of the Blessed Virgin Mary as in the Sistine Chapel in Vatican City).
The children took great delight in the aesthetic trifles. The beautiful objects with which they daily associated began to influence their conduct. They became gentler, more refined, more thoughtful, mere considerate. A young Italian boy, who could not be tamed before, soon changed and became gentle and refined. The astonished teacher one day asked him what made him so good. The boy pointed at the picture of the Madonna and said, ‘how can a fellow do bad things when she is looking at him?’
Many people could be saved from wrong doing and crime by the cultivation of the aesthetic faculties in their childhood. A love for the truly beautiful would save children from mischief, roughness of behavior and unpleasant nature. Unhappily, we do not sufficiently cultivate, either in ourselves or in our children, the sense of beauty. Yet no other pleasure is so pure, so costless and so accessible as beauty.
On the other hand, we can also understand the value of the beautiful through the pursuit of purposeful activity. Whoever gives encouragement to the pursuit of chosen, worthy purposes, to building internal concern that these be pursued carefully, painstakingly, with increasing standards of excellence – the person is extending aesthetic enjoyment. The point here is that this possibilities of  aesthetic enjoyment is not restricted to the beauties of nature and fine arts, but extends to any and every worthwhile interest pursued so whole-heartedly that  the person builds ideals for each stage of such activity and enjoys satisfaction from realizing these ideals.
One final consideration is the moral outlook. The moral outlook has in it a true aesthetic element. We saw above from Webster that taste is the power of discerning and appreciating fitness, beauty, order, congruity, proportion, symmetry, or whatever constitutes excellence. Morality is certainly an excellence. The moral person is one who has developed such a taste for, and appreciation of, moral fitness, order, congruity, and excellence that behavior and attitudes embodying these qualities give to him immediate aesthetic enjoyment.
So, our appreciation of beauty puts us in touch with the Author of all beauty. At no other time therefore do our spirits come into such close touch with the divine as when we are lost in the contemplation of the sublimity, the grandeur and the perfection of the universe; what Fr Donald B Cozzens calls ‘Transcendence.’[12] Beauty is a quality of divinity, and to live much with the beautiful is to live close to the divine.
END NOTES


[1] Webster’s Dictionary of Synonyms (Springfield, Mass Mernam, 1942)
[2] Leo Tolstoy, What is Art? as in Dickie G and Sclafoni R J (Eds), Aesthetics: A Critical Anthology.(New York: St Martin’s Press ,1977) P.59
[3] Ibid.
[4] Ibid. P 60
[5]Webster’s Dictionary of Synonyms (Springfield, Mass Mernam 1942)
[6] Walter P, the Renaissance: Studies in Art and Poetry (New York, Macmillan 1888). P 252
[7] Webster’s Dictionary of Synonyms (Springfield, Mass Mernam 1942). P 76
[8] Ibid. P 110
[9] Dewey J, Art as Experience (New York: Minton Balch, 1934)
[10] Reference to Orisen Swett Marden here is found in Kaitholil G, Make Beauty Your Target (Mumbai,Bandra: St Paul Press, 2011). P 10
[11] Cf. Ibid. Pp 12-13 
[12] Cf. Cozzens D B, the Changing Face of the Priesthood (Collegeville, Minnesota: The Liturgical Press, 2000).P 29

No comments:

Post a Comment